|

September 13, 2017

India: Supreme Court’s places of worship ruling betrays a selective reading of constitutional provisions | Tahir Mahmood

The Indian Express

Articles Of Faith

Supreme Court’s places of worship ruling betrays a selective reading of constitutional provisions

Written by Tahir Mahmood | Updated: September 13, 2017

The Supreme Court judgment in State of Gujarat v Islamic Relief Committee was explained by Satish Jha in ‘Behind SC verdict on places of worship, Article on taxpayers’ money and religion’ (IE, September 3). The reference was to Article 27 of the Constitution of India, discussed in the judgment at length. There is, however, more to the judgment than meets the eye. I have no bone to pick with the operative part of the judgment but am concerned with the court’s rather far-fetched interpretation of Article 27 and the omission of any reference to another highly relevant provision of the Constitution.
Under appeal before the apex court was the Gujarat High Court’s directive to the state government to repair religious places damaged during the communal frenzy in 2002 and recovering its costs from those guilty of the devastation. The state government came in appeal to the SC and filed before it a scheme for awarding a small compensatory contribution to the trustees of each of the damaged properties. The scheme was based on the report of a local committee which it had set up to examine the matter. The respondents in the appeal called it a “travesty of justice” but the SC approved the scheme with an observation that a “substantial part of taxpayers’ money cannot be granted for repairing religious structures”.
Placed in Part III of the Constitution relating to fundamental rights under the “Right to Freedom of Religion”, Article 27 proclaims: “No person shall be compelled to pay any taxes the proceeds of which are specifically appropriated in payment of expenses for the promotion or maintenance of any particular religion or religious denomination.” Its location in the Constitution and words are clear enough to understand that it is a part of individuals’ religious liberty and restrains the state from collecting any special tax for promoting or maintaining a particular religion.
I fail to understand how getting a damaged religious place repaired and realising its cost from those who had damaged it can be seen as “promotion or maintenance” of religion. And if it does, then the quantum of expenditure involved — be it substantial or meagre — must be irrelevant.
There is nothing in the language of Article 27 suggesting that the prohibition applies only if the amount spent is “substantial”. Who will determine, and by what criteria, whether an amount is substantial or trivial? Will the decisive voice in the matter be of the government of the day?
Another provision in the Constitution seems to be lending its weight to the SC’s conditional reading of Article 27. This is Article 290A, which says: “A sum of forty-six lakhs and fifty thousand rupees shall be charged on, and paid out of, the Consolidated Fund of the State of Kerala every year to the Travancore Devaswom Fund; and a sum of thirteen lakhs and fifty thousand rupees shall be charged on, and paid out of, the Consolidated Fund of the State of Tamil Nadu every year to the Devaswom Fund established in that State for the maintenance of Hindu temples and shrines in the territories transferred to that State on the 1st day of November, 1956, from the State of Travancore-Cochin.”
This was a religious obligation independent India had inherited from the two erstwhile princely states referred to in the Article as a precondition for their joining the Indian Union. The provision clearly clashes with the general principle of Article 27 but perhaps the payable amount, aggregating to Rs 6 million, does not qualify as a “substantial part of tax-payers’ money.”
Be it Article 290A or Article 48 — which mandates that the state protect the cow and its progeny — these provisions of the Constitution determine the nature and parameters of secularism in our country which is not absolute but restricted. This constitutional philosophy of a qualified secularism has to be accepted by us.
Our courts must, however, apply it uniformly. Deciding some cases on the basis of our concept of qualified secularism but invoking the ideal of absolute secularism in some others amounts to a judicial selectivity that does not stand to reason.
The writer is a senior law professor and an ex-member of the Law Commission of India.